Sunday, November 11, 2012

"The Moral Landscape" -- Introduction


The Introduction of Sam Harris' "The Moral Landscape" lays bare, in 26 and a half pages, the argument he will expound upon through the entire book. His argument is as follows:

 "... questions about values -- about meaning, morality, and life's larger purpose -- are really questions about the well-being of conscious creatures. Values, therefore, translate into facts that can be scientifically understood...  The more we understand ourselves at the level of the brain, the more we will see that there are right and wrong answers to questions of human values (p. 2). ... I will argue that morality should be considered an undeveloped branch of science (p. 4)." 

Essentially, Harris is arguing that acting in a moral way is acting in such a way as to increase the well-being of conscious creatures. In this paragraph, he goes on to say that brain states, as determined through the discipline of neuroscience, are universal among like-brained sentient creatures (universal among all humans, therefore) and therefore transcend the boundaries of culture. He argues that just as one disease or condition in one culture is the same disease or condition in another culture, compassion and well-being (as determined by brain state) are also the same cross-culturally. Therefore, he says, values can ultimately be right or wrong. He writes, "moral truth can be understood in the context of science." As I have come to read his presentation of the topic, he is using logic to determine what a person should do in a given situation (using a logic-based code of ethics). 

Important to discuss is Harris' refutation of the current 2 existing views of morality, as he sees them: "... People who draw their worldview from religion generally believe that moral truth exists, but only because God has woven it into the very fabric of reality; while those who lack such faith tend to think that notions of 'good' and 'evil' must be the products of evolutionary pressure and cultural invention. On the first account, to speak of 'moral truth' is, of necessity, to invoke God; on the second, it is merely to give voice to one's apish urges, cultural biases, and philosophical confusion. My purpose is to persuade you that both sides in this debate are wrong. The goal of this book is to begin a conversation about how moral truth can be understood in the context of science (p. 2)." 

His argument, he writes, is based on one, core premise: Human well-being entirely depends on events in the world and on states of the human brain. Therefore, he postulates, there must be scientific truths to be known about it. Understanding these truths in more and more detail as science progresses will force us to "draw clear distinctions between different ways of living ... judging some to be more or less ethical." Such insights would help us improve the quality of life, he writes, and in so doing draws the line between philosophical debate and practical choices we must make that affect the lives of millions. 

An important aspect to his presentation of the argument is that we are not guaranteed to resolve every single ethical dilemma immediately through science; differences of opinion will still remain, but as science improves and as we learn more and more about the world and the human brain, these opinions will be "increasingly constrained by facts (p. 3)."  A bit later in the introduction, he introduces the concept of the moral landscape, from which the title of his book is derived. 

In the same way that a mountain range has many peaks and valleys, and everything in between, so too does the moral landscape -- "a space of real and potential outcomes whose peaks correspond to the heights of potential well-being and whose valleys represent the deepest possible suffering. Different ways of thinking and behaving -- different cultural practices, ethical codes, modes of government, etc. -- will translate into movements across this landscape and, therefore, into different degrees of human flourishing. I'm not suggesting that we will necessarily discover one right answer to every moral question or a single best way for human beings to live. Some questions may admit of many answers, each more or less equivalent. However, the existence of multiple peaks on the moral landscape does not make them any less real or worthy of discovery (p. 7)." 



{To liven things up here, and to take a breather, here's a picture of the Alps I took this spring. (Pretend the peaks represent the Good Life  -- the best imaginable life, full of good health, intelligence, a fulfilled romantic life, a fulfilling and rewarding career, etc. --  and the valleys represent the Bad Life -- the worst imaginable life, full of dwindling health, starvation, loneliness, war, emotional and physical suffering, the death of several loved ones, etc. Harris goes into more detail on p. 15) }

Harris points out an important truth early on: "... Our inability to answer a question says nothing about whether the question itself has an answer... Does our inability to gather the relevant data oblige us to respect all opinions equally? Of course not. ... The fact that we may not be able to resolve specific moral dilemmas does not suggest that all competing responses to them are equally valid (p. 3)."

For the next portion of the Introduction, Harris discusses  how our two current conceptions of morality which reside on opposite ends of the political spectrum are both  incorrect and harmful, from fundamentalist religious conceptualizations of predetermined, objective morality to liberal secularists' views of completely subjective morality -- cultural tolerance (even when dealing with harmful or shameful practices) and science as an inadequate source to inform us on how we ought to live (p.11). While I cannot be sure, my own personal viewpoint is that Harris is addressing more of the second type of person (the secular, liberal scientist) in this book, so his commentary is weighed more heavily in this direction.

However, he does provide some examples of how the morality that religious individuals often adhere to is often directly in opposition to well-being. Harris gives the example of corporal punishment in schools: "There are places where it is actually legal for a teacher to beat a child with a wooden board hard enough to raise large bruises and even to break the skin. Hundreds of thousands of children are subjected to this violence each year, almost exclusively in the South. Needless to say, the rationale for this behavior is explicitly religious... "the Creator ... has told us not to spare the rod lest we spoil the child" (Proverbs 13:24, 20:30, and 23:13-14). However, if we are actually concerned about human well-being and would treat children in such a way as to promote it, we might wonder whether it is generally wise to subject little boys and girls to pain, terror, and public humiliation as a means of encouraging their cognitive and emotional development. Is there any doubt that this question has an answer? (In fact, all the research indicates that corporal punishment is a disastrous practice, leading to more violence and social pathology -- and, perversely, to greater support for corporal punishment) (p. 3)."

To address the more secular-minded, Harris presents the reader with a few common points of possible refutation and defends them using a combination of logic and real world examples:

-"Many people seem to think that a universal conception of morality requires that we find moral principles that admit of no exceptions. If, for instance, it is truly wrong to lie, it must always be wrong to lie -- and if one can find a single exception, any notion of moral truth must be abandoned. But the existence of moral truth ... does not require that we define morality in terms of unvarying moral precepts. Morality could be a lot like chess: there are surely principles that generally apply, but they might admit of important exceptions. If you want to play good chess, a principle like "don't lose your Queen" is almost always worth following. But it admits of exceptions: sometimes, it is the only thing you can do. It remains a fact, however, that from any position in a game of chess there will  be a range of objectively good moves and objectively bad ones (p. 8)." In the same way, there are objectively good moves and objectively bad ones in terms of human action, and science will dictate (with increasing accuracy) which are good, neutral, or bad.

-"Well-being is hard to define!" ... But so is the concept of 'physical health.' Currently, in developed countries, living to around age 90 is considered physically healthy. However, this is open to revision, as technology and medicine improve over time. But this does not mean that the definition of physical health is vacuous. In the same way, well-being is, though extremely difficult to pinpoint and frame at this point in our development as a species, clearly a spectrum of "better" or "worse."

-"But there may be exceptions." What if what produces well-being for me is, say, killing young children, raping their corpses, and dismembering them, as Jeffery Dahmer's idea of a life well-lived was? Does this mean that morality is to be treated subjectively? No, Harris argues. Other branches of science do not merely throw out opinions -- certain things MUST be true, and some MUST be false, just as in all other branches of science.

I will end this summary with one of my  favorite passages from these 26 pages: "It seems inevitable ... that science will gradually encompass life's deepest questions. ... Only a rational understanding of human well-being will allow billions of us to coexist peacefully, converging on the same social, political, economic, and environmental goals. A science of human flourishing may seem a long way off, but to achieve it, we much first acknowledge that the intellectual terrain actually exists (p. 7)."

And just for kicks, here's a quick link to Harris' 2010 TED talk (~ 23 minutes) on how science can answer moral questions: http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Hj9oB4zpHww In all likelihood, watching this, in addition to reading my post, will be much more informative than just reading my post. Just a hunch.

Please, discuss!

Introduction to Sherri, a Fellow Searcher

Hello dear reader of Honest Search for Truth! I figure that I should introduce myself formally (or, as "formally" as I can on a more or less informal discussion and inquiry blog), as I am working with Josh as a fellow Truth Seeker. My name is Sherri, and I am a colleague -- of sorts -- of Josh's. We met almost a decade ago, and have recently been individually driven to seek out the best possible (most rational and loving -- which I would argue are one and the same) way to live life. My goal in life, as I feel Josh's is as well, is to help as many people as possible. Additionally, I think it is imperative to, as Socrates said, "live the examined life." While I can in no way claim to be as thorough and fervent of a truth seeker as Josh is, I am extremely passionate about discussion of important topics, such as morality and the nature of existence, and I see it vital to engage in honest, unbiased inquiry into topics such as these, and to then spread reason throughout the world. I see increasing Well Being, for humanity, all other species, and the planet that sustains us all, as the single most important goal of my own life, and I am dedicated to sharing that view with as many people as possible, in hopes to convince them that this is indeed the case.

My posts, though I am also deeply interested in uncovering truths and learning all that I can about the universe and its purpose, will most often take the form of rational explanations of current societal problems, and will hopefully offer rational solutions to those problems.

At present, I am agnostic in regards to a Conscious Agent (ie, God). But I see Morality, and all that it implies, as the single most important discussion piece in the world today, because how people conceptualize morality determines how they act -- meaning, essentially, that the differing views on morality are arguably the cause for all of the current societal problems.

In order to learn more about morality, Josh graciously gave me a book by philosopher and neuroscience expert Sam Harris, entitled, "The Moral Landscape." Though I have listened to Dr. Harris speak in a handful of internet videos, I wanted to get a very good grasp of his position, both to understand one expert's view and to further develop my own.

A good place for me to start contributing to Honest Search for Truth would be for me to share my findings as I read with an audience. That way, I will be able to learn the art of skillful summary (and will thereby develop my grasp of the material), and readers will be able to (hopefully!) garner the main points within the book in a more concise manner. In these posts, I will be aiming to solely report summaries of chapters. I am, in these posts anyway, going to stray away from including my own personal thoughts/rational reflections on the matter, and if I do include these, I will be absolutely sure to make sure to distinguish between summarizing Harris and personal commentary.

In my next post (which I will write momentarily), I will summarize the Introduction portion of "The Moral Landscape," which lays the foundation for the remainder of the book.

Cheers!

--A Fellow Truth Seeker and Lover of the Light

Wednesday, October 24, 2012

What is Inside of the Box?

"We will never know whether or not God actually exists," is a phrase I have heard time and time again while discussing my search for truth. Here is why I think this is a ridiculous statement!

Ok. Jim has a box that Larry cannot see into, and there may or may not be a marker inside of the box. Now Jim has a question for Larry: "Is there a marker inside of the box?"

Larry certainly can't tell me whether or not there is a marker in the box right now, because he can't see into the box. Jim decides to try to figure out whether or not there is a marker in the box, but Larry tells him "it is impossible to know whether or not there is a marker inside of the box."

This is an extremely prideful statement for Larry to make. Saying that he knows that it is impossible to know, would be to say that he has already ruled out every past, present, and future method for determining whether or not there is a marker inside of the box. How does Larry know that it is impossible, if he hasn't even made an honest attempt at the possible methods for finding out.

You know what? I think that Larry is lazy and just wants to stay in his comfort zone. His life is simple and figured out based off of what he currently thinks about this devious marker, and questioning his belief would force more questions.

It is far easier to say that it is impossible as an excuse to not try. Unfortunately, Larry would have to have already exhausted every methodology to determine that it is, indeed, impossible to know.

Here are a few things that we thought were impossible to know in the past:

  • How to create vaccines
  • How to build prosthetic limbs
  • How to send a man to the moon
  • What the atomic structure of water is
  • How many membranes certain types of bacteria have

If Larry had been asked about these things 1000 years ago, and said "it is impossible to know," he would have been very wrong.

Now, it is possible for there to be things that are impossible for us to know about. For example, did Napoleon spit in a pond on the third day of June while he was 19 years old thinking about how much he likes good wine and cheese? This, probably is impossible to know, unless we develop time travel and ask him.

But if something really is impossible to know about, is it worth it to bet your life on something you can't know about?

The Difference Between Searching for Jesus and Searching for Truth

Having attended protestant-based churches for my entire life, I have noticed a unifying goal: searching for Jesus. This includes a longing to know him, experience him, glorify him, and share the good news about him with others.

I have found that there is a fundamental difference between seeking Jesus, and seeking truth. I will use Christianity as an example here, but feel free to insert whichever worldview you prefer. My argument should apply to many belief systems.

The first thing many Christian readers will think here is "But Josh! Jesus is the truth, so when you search for truth, you are searching for Jesus!"

Allow me a few paragraphs to explain why I do not think this is the case
------------------------------------------------------.

1. Someone searching for truth believes things only based off of their true-ness, and devotes their time and energy to examining arguments and evidence. If this person were to end up believing in Jesus based off of evidence, then they believe in Jesus because he is true.

2. Someone searching for Jesus assumes that Jesus is true, and devotes their time and effort to deepening their relationship with him. This person believes in truth because it is Jesus.

It is possible for someone searching for truth to end up believing in Jesus if the evidence points towards him. The logical conclusion of a search for truth that points towards Jesus is to follow him, accept the gospel, and believe (once again, a search for truth could end up with the searcher being an Atheist, in which case it makes the most sense to simply enjoy the one life you have and not bother with silly religious blather). This type of belief in Jesus does not, as I have defined things, made that person someone who fundamentally searches for Jesus. The person is most fundamentally someone who searches for truth, and the evidence just so happens to point towards one specific religious leader (who, in this case, would also happen to be God).

Keep in mind that a search for truth can point in any direction--it does not decide where it is going to end up at the beginning. Instead, it sets up a framework for determining which things are true and which things are false. This means that a searcher for truth could end up believing in anything or nothing, depending on where the arguments and evidence leads. The important thing in searching for truth is the evidence.

It is not generally possible for someone searching for Jesus to end up believing something else. Not caring about evidence, or more commonly, assuming that the evidence overwhelmingly points towards one's own beliefs without ever actually looking at the evidence either way. I have found that this type of belief is based off of social pressure (including parental pressure) or emotional experiences.

Summary:
Someone who follows Jesus based off of evidence is someone who most fundamentally believes in him based off of searching for truth. They believe in Jesus because he is true. This is in stark contrast to someone who believes in truth because it is Jesus. 

A final thought. Searching for Jesus lacks distinction. By this I mean that if you pick a religion or worldview for reasons other than evidence, you essentially roll the dice and hope that what you picked it true. Searching for truth has distinction, because it can fairly distinguish between all other kinds of worldviews.

Monday, October 15, 2012

Has God ever healed an amputee?

For many years I have been curious about whether or not praying for someone when they are sick has an effect. Having spent dozens of hours doing so myself, I certainly hope that I haven't been wasting my time.

Unfortunately, after examining several studies concerning the effectiveness of prayer, I came to the conclusion that no prayer study done so far is legitimate in answering the question it seeks to ask (If you know of any good ones, please let me know). Lacking a valid study on the effectiveness of prayer, I considered my personal experience growing up as a Christian. What I remember is that people with mild illnesses were often 'healed' thanks to the prayers of the church (myself included), but those with life threatening illnesses didn't seem to make it.

In particular, there was one person who died at a very young age, despite the fervent prayers of an entire church.

So, does prayer work when it comes to healing the sick? I recognize that there are other reasons to pray, such as glorifying God, expressing dependence upon him, submitting to him, etc. What I am currently curious about is whether or not asking God to heal one of your loved ones has a physical impact.

Consider the following question: Has anyone ever been healed of losing a limb or an organ?

If you have a recorded instance of this happening, please let me know. As of yet, it seems to me that no amputee has ever been healed through prayer (although some cool scientists have made prosthetic limbs and replaced organs).

Does this mean that God has a special plan for amputees? If so, why did He single out the amputees as opposed to people with other kinds of illnesses?

Sunday, October 14, 2012

Infinite Sets an Impossibility?

If any readers are familiar with Thomas Aquinas, or simply arguments pertaining to the existence of God having to do with the impossibility of an infinite set, then hopefully this post will be enjoyable.

Here is an example of an impossible infinite set:

Premise 1: The universe has existed forever
Premise 2: Time flows forward at a finite rate

Conclusion: It would be impossible for us to ever reach the 'present' time, because there will always be non-zero amounts of time that have to pass before we will reach the present.

Another way of saying this is as follows: If time goes backwards into the past, and there was never a beginning of time, we would never reach the present. There would quite simply be 10 more years before 10 more years before 10 more years, etc. before we ever reached the present. In fact, you would never reach any point in time, because there would always be another 10 years (actually an infinite number of years) before you ever reached any given point.

Tonight I was also considering the 'traveling half the distance' paradigm. This argument is as follows:
If you continue traveling half the distance from point A to point B, you will never reach point B. You will get pretty darn close, but there will always be space between the two points.

I have to go study for a test now, but I wanted to jot down my ideas and throw them out there for consideration and comment! I acknowledge there are key differences between the two concepts I have introduced. Also, there are many issues to bring up, especially concerning the first two premises of argument 1.

Sunday, October 7, 2012

The Suspicious Coincidence of 'Objective' Morality which lines up with Natural Expectations

Here is the main point of this post:   

Out of the set of possible moralities that God could have chosen, he happened to pick one that lined up excellently with a non-objective morality that would have been evolutionarily generated.

If you are not familiar with both the moral argument for God's existence and evolutionary biology, what I just said probably did not seem significant. My statement is a response to the first chapter of Mere Christianity, by C.S. Lewis. The remainder of this post is an explanation as to why my previous statement is relevant to Lewis' work.

------------------------------------------------

If God exists, then he has the power to define what is right and wrong, no? God is omnipotent and created everything. Therefore, he is afforded the right to define what is morally right and what is morally wrong for everyone. He has the authority to do so because he is God.

These thoughts fall under the ideology of divine command theory.

But is there another possible source for objective morality other than an all-powerful God? While multiple scientists, most notably Sam Harris,  have attempted to assert that there is, I think that they have ultimately failed to do so (for now I will leave it to William Lane Craig to demonstrate the failure of Harris; see the debates I linked for info on this). Before continuing, let me recommend a few  resources on this subject for those who are new to the objective morality debate.

Here is a worthwhile, 5 minute video from Richard Dawkins on the subject. I highly recommend watching it before continuing your reading.
  • http://bigthink.com/ideas/17055
Here are two debates on this subject, if you are interested in delving deeper. They are long, but very worth while:
  • http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=rq1QjXe3IYQ
  • http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=yqaHXKLRKzg
It would also be a great idea to read the first chapter of Mere Christianity by C.S. Lewis!

Anyway, if there is no higher authority, it impossible for a universal Right and Wrong to exist. The is no objective Good or Evil. Why? Consider the following scenario:

Person A thinks that it is morally wrong for people to be homosexual. Person B thinks that it is not morally wrong for people to be homosexual. Who is right?

Well, both of them in their own eyes. As long as there is no higher authority for either one to appeal to, neither can say that the other is wrong. Both people define a personal morality for themselves.

This does not mean that we have the innate sense that objective morals exist. This, we most certainly do possess.

Now we need to find and explanation for our perception of objective morality. Any explanation for our innate feelings on this subject must meet two criteria. 1) The explanation must be universal and cross-cultural, because morals are wide-spread and similar throughout the global population. 2) The explanation must allow for certain types of cultural variance, because various cultures do exhibit fluctuations from the overall trend.

There are two possible explanations that I know of:
  1. A higher being created the human race with a sense of objective morality
  2. Through the process of evolution via natural selection, along with cultural interactions, humans developed a sense of objective morality.
Keep in mind that in explanation 1, objective morals actually exist. In explanation 2, objective morals do not exist (it only seems like they do because we have been culturally and genetically programmed to think so).

Both explanations 1 and 2 are valid when it comes to why humans have a sense of objective morality.

HOWEVER, and now we are getting back to my main point here, there is an infinite set of morals which God could have chosen to make objectively right. In addition, the set of morals which could have been generated due to evolution via natural selection is limited.

For example, God could choose to make murder objectively right. He could also choose to make doing hand stands 23 times a day objectively wrong. He could do anything at all that he wanted.

On the other hand, perceived morals generated via evolution could not make certain kinds of things seem morally right or wrong. It would be a rarity (not an impossibility, but a rarity), to see a perceived moral Right generated which would hinder the fitness of a population of humans (Although certain exceptions must be allowed because emergent phenomena such as culture and religion have the ability to create anomalies).

Let's nail down one concrete example that can be used to demonstrate the contrast here:
God could make it morally obligatory for people to kill all of their children. You probably feel a sense of disgust at this, but if God had created you with the innate sense that killing your children was Right, then you would not feel that sense of disgust. Rather, you would feel disgust at people who didn't kill their children.

On the other hand, it would be impossible for an evolutionarily generated morality to contain such an idea. This is because killing one's children reduces one's evolutionary fitness to zero.

Here is a brief list of perceived morals which make sense from an evolutionary/meme-based standpoint. If you have questions on any of these at all, PLEASE ask! I don't want to shot-gun you with a list and expect you to agree with me. In fact, I think that unless this makes sense to you based off of your previous education in biology, you should neither agree nor disagree with me until you gain the necessary knowledge. As a biologist myself, I am more than happy to help you gain that knowledge.
  • The existence of strict societal rules regarding marriage/mate choice
  • Why rape seems wrong
  • Why murder seems wrong
  • Why lying seems wrong
  • Altruistic acts such as dying for one's family
  • Nationalistic acts such as dying for one's country (google 'memes biology dawkins' for info on that)
  • Why stealing seems wrong
And so we will return to my main point once again:

Out of the set of possible moralities that God could have chosen, he happened to pick one that lined up excellently with a non-objective morality that would have been evolutionarily generated.

To me, this seems like a suspicious coincidence. Then again, God could have simply created a natural world which would have undergone the generation of life such that environmental pressure would cause a perceived set of morals which lined up with what he had already purposed the objective morality to be. However, there is no reason why an omnipotent being would need to make his morality line up with natural causes. If the 'God made nature do it' argument is to be followed here, then we find ourselves in scenarios such as 'God created through evolution' or 'God made the universe with the big bang.' In every scenario like that, God adds nothing to the equation.

And so we come back once again. God could have picked any morality. It just so happens that the morality we have lines up very nicely with what you would expect from a society that evolved via natural selection.

What we have here, ladies and gentlemen, is a suspicious coincidence.

Saturday, September 29, 2012

Parable of the Fallen Bridge

Once there was a group of three climbers who were trying to reach the peak of a gigantic and treacherous mountain.On their way to the summit, they came across a deep chasm spanning a long distance. As they neared the edge, they realized that a bridge crossing the expanse had recently fallen.

Looking down at the remnants of the bridge, the climbers noticed nine people clinging to the ropes and boards. The climbers called to them, but unfortunately, none of them were strong enough to climb up and save themselves.



The first climber looked down, and felt very uncomfortable at the thought of all the lifting and working that would be involved in saving them. He reasoned to himself: "Helping all of the people would be an impossible task. I'm only one person. Even if I tried I wouldn't make much of a difference." Then, pretending not to see the people, he continued on his way up the mountain.

The second climber looked down, and felt a surge of compassion. Not wanting to look inconsiderate like the first climber, he stooped down and threw out a rope. After working for a few minutes, he pulled up one or two of the hapless individuals. Suddenly he realized that it was taking real work to save the needy, and decided he would much rather go on with his life. The second climber thought to himself: "I have certainly done all that can be expected of me. Normal people would have helped much less. After all, I did more than the first climber." Then, ignoring the cries from the people below, he continued on his way up the mountain.

The third climber looked down, and thought to himself: "If I were in distress and holding on for my life, and someone else had the opportunity to help me, I would want to be saved." He then abandoned his aspirations for reaching the peak of the mountain, and started pulling people up. He continued to do for the rest of his life.

The third climber never successfully saved every person on the fallen bridge. He only saved as many as he could.
 -----------------------------------------------------------

"In round numbers there are 7 billion people in the world. Thus, with an estimated 925 million hungry people in the world, 13.1 percent, or almost 1 in 7 people are hungry."

"Children who are poorly nourished suffer up to 160 days of illness each year. Poor nutrition plays a role in at least half of the 10.9 million child deaths each year--five million deaths."

"The world produces enough food to feed everyone. World agriculture produces 17 percent more calories per person today than it did 30 years ago, despite a 70 percent population increase."


Which climber are you?


All statistics taken from: www.worldhunger.org
But why stop at world hunger? There are many fallen bridges in our world.



Wednesday, September 26, 2012

Doubt your Doubts?

Today I heard the phrase "doubt your doubts" one too many times. It was when a concerned Christian was attempting to desuade their fellow believer from asking serious questions about the validity of their faith.

If I may, I must go on a short rant.

What does "doubt your doubts" even mean?? It seems so witty and savy, turning the doubting tables on the doubts themselves, but there is no actual substance to the statement.

For example, "doubt your doubts" could be countered by "doubt your doubting of doubts." This could in turn be countered by "doubt your doubting of your doubting of doubts." And so on and so forth.

I don't understand why someone would find security in a belief system based off of this phrase. "Doubt your doubts" means nothing.

Consider the following story: A person happens to believe that the world is flat. They are presented with some arguments in favor of the sphericallness of the earth. A fellow flat-earthest consoles them by saying "doubt your doubts!" The person goes on believing that the world is flat because they doubted their doubts about the flattness of the earth.

It is much better to dwell in a realm with substance. If you have a doubt, ask yourself why you have it. Perhaps you want an honest answer to a question. Perhaps you are curious. Perhaps you have personal experience or wisdom relating to the validity of certain kinds of claims. Simply doubting doubts does nothing. Addressing the doubts by examining evidence allows you to make progress.

So please, if you have ever heard the phrase "doubt your doubts," I would encourage you to at least doubt your doubting of doubts. Even better than that would be to start looking around for valid types of evidence and coherent streams of logic that pertain to your doubts so that you can draw some legit conclusions.

Rant: completed.

Hedonism


Hedonism is the school of thought that the acquisition of happiness is the ultimate goal of every person. According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, "Motivational hedonism is the claim that only pleasure or pain motivates us."

'But surely not!' You say. 'We do things that harm ourselves all the time!' This is is true in a sense. For example, giving to charity, becoming a martyr, doing a hard workout, or commuting suicide all seem to harm us.

It may be helpful to note that 'net' happiness is what is sought after. This means that we may do things that are painful, such as taking a biology test or the MCAT. BUT, we only do these things because we think that we will gain a greater amount of happiness from doing so.

I would argue that even in cases of suicide, people are attempting to gain the most happiness. A suicidal person sees the future as containing a net negative happiness, and so decides to end their life.

On a less bleak note, I think that everything we do is motivated by a search for happiness. Going to school, going to work, helping someone with homework, getting married, having kids, going on a search for truth, we do all of things with our own best interest in mind.

Tuesday, September 25, 2012

4 Stats on World Hunger

Lately I have been trying to raise awareness about various humanist efforts. Here are a few facts about world hunger that everyone should be aware of. All my stats come from this website: http://www.worldhunger.org/articles/Learn/world%20hunger%20facts%202002.htm. If you need specifics on the meaning of certain terms or would like more information, go check out www.worldhunger.org!

4 Stats on World Hunger
  1. The world produces enough food to feed everyone
  2. In 2010, there were 925 million hungry people
  3. The primary cause of world hunger is poverty
  4. The number of people who are hungry in the world is increasing

I find it quite unfortunate that we produce enough food for everyone, and yet not everyone gets food.

I will also point out that the increase in the number of people who are hungry is probably related to the global population increase. An increase in population complicates the process of keeping people fed. Unfortunately, feeding people also increases the world population. This means that fixing the problem actually makes the problem harder to fix.

Anyway, a complicated issue to be sure. Hopefully we can make progress!

Specific References:
  • http://www.worldhunger.org/articles/Learn/world%20hunger%20facts%202002.htm#Number_of_hungry_people_in_the_world
  • http://www.worldhunger.org/articles/Learn/world%20hunger%20facts%202002.htm#Does_the_world_produce_enough_food_to_feed_everyone
  • http://www.worldhunger.org/articles/Learn/world%20hunger%20facts%202002.htm#What_are_the_causes_of_hunger
  •  http://www.worldhunger.org/articles/Learn/world%20hunger%20facts%202002.htm#Progress_in_reducing_the_number_of_hungry_people_

Monday, September 24, 2012

What if I told you that someone died today whom you could have saved?

I realize this is a very complicated issue, and I haven't even begun to address it with a few paragraphs of text. Right now all I want to do is start a conversation. Hopefully it will be a conversation that will result in lives being saved.

But really, what if I told you that someone died today whom you could have saved?

Yes, this is likely going to be depressing. Most people will probably choose to ignore this so that they can remain comfortable.

Anyway, the truth is that there are people that died today who could have been saved by you and I, had we chosen to take the initiative.

Let's say that the person living next door to me is starving. They never ask me for food, but I know that they are starving. Instead of doing something about the problem, I heat up my microwave dinner, plop down on the couch, start watching TV, throw away the vegetables that I didn't feel like eating, and after a few weeks, my neighbor dies of starvation. What kind of person am I?

Due to massive jumps in technology, the globe has been radically connected. Thanks to this website: http://www.worldhunger.org/articles/Learn/world%20hunger%20facts%202002.htm, we have plenty of statistics on world hunger. In addition, we have the ability to do something to effect the number of starving people. This drastically increases the number of 'neighbors' that we have.

Sure, it might cost us time and money, but if we tried, we could prevent some of the starving people from starving.

Thank you to those who are already trying to make a difference!

Sunday, September 23, 2012

Humanist Maximalism

The ultimate goal of Humanist Maximalism is to obtain maximal happiness for humanity in terms of quality of life and percentage of the global population that is effected. If this goal were reached, 100% of humans would be extremely happy.


Because this primary goal is very likely impossible, a secondary goal must be introduced. Namely, that the maximum amount of improvement towards the primary goal must be realized.

Here are a few examples of what a Human Maximalist would attempt to accomplish:
  • End poverty
  • End slavery
  • End war
  • Modify human society such that we won't destroy our environment
  • Provide education to everyone who wants it
It is quite obvious that these are lofty goals. Keep in mind, however, that just because a goal is lofty does not mean that it is impossible to accomplish it. In addition, if everyone had the mentality that lofty goals should not be pursued because it would take a lot of work, then the world would be a terrible place.

Because of this, it is most helpful to attempt to make as much progress towards each of these goals as is humanly possible.

As a Human Maximalist, I hope to develop and carry out strategies to make as much progress as I can towards making as many people as possible as happy as I can make them.

Monday, September 17, 2012

Honors Thesis Outline

Hi everyone!
I've been making a lot of progress on my Honors Thesis. Here is the road map that I will use to press forward. If you have any suggestions for additional resources I should tackle in my Literature Review, let me know!



Honors Thesis Outline
A Biologist’s Perspective on the Fine-Tuning Argument


· Introduction
o   Topic and Purpose of Thesis
§  Topic: The fine-tuning of physical parameters in phase space
§  Purpose: To examine the fine-tuning of four parameters
·         The Speed of Light
·         Planck’s Constant
·         The Gravitational Constant
·         The Cosmological Constant
o   Literature Review: History of Fine-Tuning
§  Explain major contributions up to this point
·         Lawrence Henderson – The Fitness of the Environment
o   1913
·         Robert Dicke, 1961
·         Fred Hoyle – Intelligent Universe
o   1984
·         John Gribbin and Martin Rees – Cosmic Coincidences
o   1989
·         William Lane Craig
·         Stephen Hawking – The Grand Design
o   2010
·         Victor Stenger – The Fallacy of Fine-Tuning
o   2011


· Background- provide reader with necessary information to understand parameters
o   Biology
§  Define Life
§  Outline requirements for life
§  Planet, Solar System, and Universe level parameters
o   Parameters in phase space
§  Dimensionless numbers
o   Physics
§  Light
·         Relativity
§  Planck’s Constant
§  Gravity
§  Cosmology
·         Cosmic Inflation
§  Multiverse Theory
·         String Theory


· Main Argument
o   Phrase argument utilizing sharpness of peaks and half-height widths for parameters
§  The slope, or sharpness, of peaks corresponds to how finely-tuned a parameter must be.
·         Examples
o   As the Gravitational constant is made larger or smaller, the universe rapidly becomes unsuitable for life.
§  The Gravitational Constant has a sharp peak.
o   As the speed of light is made larger or smaller, the universe slowly becomes unsuitable for life.
§  The speed of light has a curved peak.
o   Address objections
§  Additional peaks may exist for individual parameters
·         These hypothetical peaks should be disregarded because of their speculative nature.
§  Changing multiple parameters at once may introduce additional possibilities
·          Once again, it is better to hold all but one parameter constant and measure the steepness of individual peaks that speculate as to how life would be affected by combinations of changes.


· Response to Stenger
o   Examine Stenger’s reasoning concerning the speed of light.
§  Holding all else constant, the speed of light can be fine-tuned
·         Utilize the height of a door analogy
·         Address complications introduced by relativity.
·         Address complications introduced by the granular nature of the universe.
o   Stenge
o   Stenger’s reasoning concerning the speed of light is the same for the speed of light as it is for Planck’s Constant and the Gravitational Constant.
o   Because the speed of light displays fine-tuning, Planck’s Constant and the Gravitational Constant also display fine-tuning.
o   Establish the Cosmological Constant as a parameter which is fine-tuned.
§  Stenger admits that the Cosmological Constant is ‘up for discussion.’


· Address Additional Objections to Fine-Tuning
o   Multiverse
§  General explanation of Multiverse theory
·         Not enough evidence to support Multiverse Theory at this point
§  If Multiverse Theory were supported, additional characteristics of the Multiverse would need to be established before it would affect the fine-tuning argument.
·         The number of universes would need to be high enough to make the odds possible
·         Parameters would need to differ from universe to universe
§  If the existence and certain characteristics of the multiverse can be established, the fine-tuning argument will become invalid (unless a secondary fine-tuning argument applies to the formation of the multiverse).
o   Life Could Evolve Differently
§  Evolution will have a significant effect on planet and solar system parameters (for example, the speed of light), but will have no bearing on universe level parameters (Gravity, Planck’s Constant, and the Cosmological Constant).
§  Evolution will drive life towards peaks, thereby generating steep slopes.
·         Does not apply to universe level parameters.


· Conclusions
o   Certain parameters display fine-tuning.
§  The Speed of Light – curved peak
§  Planck’s Constant – sharp peak
§  The Gravitational Constant – sharp peak
§  The Cosmological Constant – sharp peak
o   The three ‘sharp-peaked’ parameters are sufficient to demonstrate that the universe is not fine-tuned for life due to chance.

Saturday, September 8, 2012

Website!!!

While I can't pretend to know anything about web sites, I now have one.

If you are interested in checking things out during this preliminary stage, feel free to go snoop around! The only thing you will find there right now is a link to a presentation I have created. The presentation is a work in progress. If you go there now, you will find some fun stuff, but there are many loose ends. I will be working on it every day or so adding on new material and editing. I think the presentation is pretty cool. =D

www.honestsearchfortruth.com

Sunday, August 12, 2012

Neopolitan's Philosophical Blog

As an avid searcher for truth, it brings me great joy when others think about deep stuff. It makes me extra happy when others do that thinking well, and are then brave and nice enough to share their thoughts with the rest of us.

Over the past few weeks I have been exploring a fantastic new blog: neopolitan's philosophical blog

When I first discovered it I felt like a squirrel in a peanut factory, Sheldon Cooper (Big Bang Theory) at Comic-Con, or Al Gore in a room full of people dying to hear about global warming.

(Side note- I actually do research on global climate change and have a lot of respect for Al Gore.) (I also attend Comic-Con, and have a lot of respect for Sheldon) (I do not have strong feelings either way when it comes to peanuts. Squirrels, I love.)

Anyway, neo's blog is almost as cool as Neil deGrasse Tyson's tie collection: http://neildegrassetieson.tumblr.com/

As you can see you followed the link, that is saying a lot.

Go read neo's blog!!!

http://neophilosophical.blogspot.com/